Positivismo giuridico
Legal positivism is a philosophy of law that emphasizes the conventional nature of law—that it is socially constructed. According to legal positivism, law is synonymous with positive norms, questo è, norms made by the legislator or considered as common law or case law. Formal criteria of law’s origin, law enforcement and legal effectiveness are all sufficient for social norms to be considered law. Legal positivism does not base law on divine commandments, motivo, or human rights. Come questione storica, positivism arose in opposition to classical natural law theory, according to which there are necessary moral constraints on the content of law.
Legal positivism does not imply an ethical justification for the content of the law, nor a decision for or against the obedience to law. Positivists do not judge laws by questions of justice or humanity, but merely by the ways in which the laws have been created. This includes the view that judges make new law in deciding cases not falling clearly under a legal rule. Practicing, deciding or tolerating certain practices of law can each be considered a way of creating law.
Within legal doctrine, legal positivism would be opposed to sociological jurisprudence and hermeneutics of law, which study the concrete prevailing circumstances of statutory interpretation in society.
The word “positivism” was probably first used to draw attention to the idea that law is “positive” or “posited,” as opposed to being “natural” in the sense of being derived from natural law or morality.
Sommario
The Pedigree Thesis
La tesi della separabilità
Inclusive vs. Exclusive Positivism
The Discretion Thesis
Classic Criticisms of Positivism
Fuller’s Internal Morality of Law
Positivism and Legal Principles
The Semantic Sting
Riferimenti e approfondimenti
1. The Pedigree Thesis
The pedigree thesis asserts that legal validity is a function of certain social facts. Prendendo pesantemente in prestito da Jeremy Bentham, John Austin argues that the principal distinguishing feature of a legal system is the presence of a sovereign who is habitually obeyed by most people in the society, ma non nell'abitudine di obbedire a un determinato superiore umano (Austin 1995, P. 166). Secondo Austin, una regola R è giuridicamente valida (questo è, è una legge) in una società S se e solo se R è comandato dal sovrano in S ed è accompagnato dalla minaccia di una sanzione. The severity of the threatened sanction is irrelevant; any general sovereign imperative supported by a threat of even the smallest harm is a law.
Austin’s command theory of law is vulnerable to a number of criticisms. One problem is that there appears to be no identifiable sovereign in democratic societies. In the United States, Per esempio, the ultimate political power seems to belong to the people, who elect lawmakers to represent their interests. Elected lawmakers have the power to coerce behavior but are regarded as servants of the people and not as repositories of sovereign power. The voting population, d'altra parte, seems to be the repository of ultimate political authority yet lacks the immediate power to coerce behavior. Così, in democracies like that of the United States, the ultimate political authority and the power to coerce behavior seem to reside in different entities.
A second problem has to do with Austin’s view that the sovereign lawmaking authority is incapable of legal limitation. Secondo Austin, a sovereign cannot be legally constrained because no person (or body of persons) can coerce herself (or itself). Since constitutional provisions limit the authority of the legislative body to make laws, Austin is forced to argue that what we refer to as constitutional law is really not law at all; Piuttosto, it is principally a matter of “positive morality” (Austin 1977, P. 107).
Austin’s view is difficult to reconcile with constitutional law in the United States. Courts regard the procedural and substantive provisions of the constitution as constraints on legal validity. The Supreme Court has held, Per esempio, that “an unconstitutional act is not a law; it confers no rights; it imposes no duties; it is, in legal contemplation, as inoperative as though it had never been passed.” (Norton v. Shelby County, 118 U.S. 425 (1886)). Inoltre, these constraints purport to be legal constraints: the Supremacy Clause of Article VI of the Constitution states that “[t]his Constitution … shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby.”
The most influential criticisms of Austin’s version of the pedigree thesis, Tuttavia, owe to H. l. UN. Hart’s seminal work, Il concetto di diritto. Hart points out that Austin’s theory provides, at best, a partial account of legal validity because it focuses on one kind of rule, namely that which requires citizens “to do or abstain from certain actions, whether they wish to or not” (Hart 1994, P. 81). While every legal system must contain so-called primary rules that regulate citizen behavior, Hart believes a system consisting entirely of the kind of liberty restrictions found in the criminal law is, at best, a rudimentary or primitive legal system.
Dal punto di vista di Hart, Austin’s emphasis on coercive force leads him to overlook the presence of a second kind of primary rule that confers upon citizens the power to create, modificare, ed estinguere diritti e obblighi in altre persone. Come sottolinea Hart, le norme che regolano la formazione dei contratti e dei testamenti non possono plausibilmente essere qualificate come restrizioni alla libertà assistite dalla minaccia di una sanzione. These rules empower persons to structure their legal relations within the coercive framework of the law-a feature that Hart correctly regards as one of “law’s greatest contributions to social life.” The operation of power-conferring primary rules, according to Hart, indicates the presence of a more sophisticated system for regulating behavior.
But what ultimately distinguishes societies with full-blown systems of law from those with only rudimentary or primitive forms of law is that the former have, in addition to first-order primary rules, secondary meta-rules that have as their subject matter the primary rules themselves:
[Regole secondarie] si può dire che si collocano tutti su un livello diverso dalle regole primarie, perché riguardano tutte tali regole; nel senso che mentre le regole primarie riguardano le azioni che gli individui devono o non devono compiere, queste regole secondarie riguardano tutte le stesse regole primarie. Essi specificano il modo in cui le norme primarie possono essere accertate in modo definitivo, introdotto, eliminato, vario, e il fatto della loro violazione definitivamente accertato (Hart 1994, P. 92).
Hart distingue tre tipi di norme secondarie che segnano il passaggio da forme primitive di diritto a sistemi giuridici completi: (1) la regola del riconoscimento, quale “specifico[sì] una o più caratteristiche il cui possesso mediante una regola suggerita è considerato un’indicazione affermativa e conclusiva che è una regola del gruppo ad essere sostenuta dalla pressione sociale che esercita” (Hart 1994, P. 92); (2) la regola del cambiamento, che consente ad una società di aggiungere, rimuovere, e modificare le regole valide; e (3) la regola di giudizio, che fornisce un meccanismo per determinare se una regola valida è stata violata. Dal punto di vista di Hart, Poi, ogni società dotata di un ordinamento giuridico completo ha necessariamente una norma di riconoscimento che articola criteri di validità giuridica che includono disposizioni per la realizzazione, modificare e giudicare la legge. La legge lo è, per usare la famosa frase di Hart, “l’unione di regole primarie e secondarie” (Hart 1994, P. 107). Austin theory fails, dal punto di vista di Hart, because it fails to acknowledge the importance of secondary rules in manufacturing legal validity.
Hart also finds fault with Austin’s view that legal obligation is essentially coercive. According to Hart, there is no difference between the Austinian sovereign who governs by coercing behavior and the gunman who orders someone to hand over her money. In both cases, the subject can plausibly be characterized as being “obliged” to comply with the commands, but not as being “duty-bound” or “obligated” to do so (Hart 1994, P. 80). Dal punto di vista di Hart, the application of coercive force alone can never give rise to an obligation-legal or otherwise.
Legal rules are obligatory, according to Hart, because people accept them as standards that justify criticism and, in extreme cases, punishment of deviations:
What is necessary is that there should be a critical reflective attitude to certain patterns of behavior as a common standard, and that this should display itself in criticism (including self-criticism), demands for conformity, and in acknowledgements that such criticism and demands are justified, all of which find their characteristic expression in the normative terminology of ‘ought’, ‘must’, and ‘should’, and ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ (Hart 1994, P. 56).
The subject who reflectively accepts the rule as providing a standard that justifies criticism of deviations is said to take “the internal point of view” towards it.
Dal punto di vista di Hart, it would be too much to require that the bulk of the population accept the rule of recognition as the ultimate criteria for legal validity: “the reality of the situation is that a great proportion of ordinary citizens-perhaps a majority-have no general conception of the legal structure or its criteria of validity” (Hart 1994, P. 111). Invece, Hart argues that what is necessary to the existence of a legal system is that the majority of officials take the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition and its criteria of validity. All that is required of citizens is that they generally obey the primary rules that are legally valid according to the rule of recognition.
Così, dal punto di vista di Hart, there are two minimum conditions sufficient and necessary for the existence of a legal system: “On the one hand those rules of behavior which are valid according to the system’s ultimate criteria of validity must be generally obeyed, e, d'altra parte, its rules of recognition specifying the criteria of legal validity and its rules of change and adjudication must be effectively accepted as common public standards of official behavior by its officials” (Hart 1994, P. 113).
Hart’s view is vulnerable to the same criticism that he levels against Austin. Hart rejects Austin’s view because the institutional application of coercive force can no more give rise to an obligation than can the application of coercive force by a gunman. But the situation is no different if the gunman takes the internal point of view towards his authority to make such a threat. Despite the gunman’s belief that he is entitled to make the threat, the victim is obliged, but not obligated, to comply with the gunman’s orders. The gunman’s behavior is no less coercive because he believes he is entitled to make the threat.
Allo stesso modo, in the minimal legal system, only the officials of the legal system take the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition that endows them with authority to make, execute, adjudicate, and enforce the rules. The mere presence of a belief in the officials that they are entitled to make law cannot give rise to an obligation in other people to comply with their enactments any more than the presence of a belief on the part of a gunman that he is entitled to issue orders gives rise to an obligation in the victim to comply with those orders. Hart’s minimal legal system is no less coercive than Austin’s legal system.
2. La tesi della separabilità
The second thesis comprising the foundation of legal positivism is the separability thesis. Nella sua forma più generale, the separability thesis asserts that law and morality are conceptually distinct. Questa formulazione astratta può essere interpretata in diversi modi. Per esempio, Klaus Faber (1996) lo interpreta come un'affermazione di meta-livello secondo cui la definizione di legge deve essere completamente priva di nozioni morali. Questa interpretazione implica che ogni riferimento a considerazioni morali nella definizione delle relative nozioni di diritto, validità legale, and legal system is inconsistent with the separability thesis.
Più comunemente, the separability thesis is interpreted as making only an object-level claim about the existence conditions for legal validity. As H.L.A. Hart describes it, the separability thesis is no more than the “simple contention that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands of morality, anche se in realtà lo hanno fatto spesso” (Hart 1994, pp. 181-82). Insofar as the object-level interpretation of the separability thesis denies it is a necessary truth that there are moral constraints on legal validity, implica l'esistenza di un possibile ordinamento giuridico in cui non esistono vincoli morali alla validità giuridica.
UN. Inclusive vs. Exclusive Positivism
Sebbene tutti i positivisti siano d'accordo sul fatto che esistono possibili sistemi giuridici senza vincoli morali sulla validità legale, ci sono opinioni contrastanti sulla possibilità che esistano sistemi giuridici con tali vincoli. Secondo il positivismo inclusivo (noto anche come incorporazionismo e positivismo morbido), è possibile che la regola di riconoscimento di una società incorpori vincoli morali sul contenuto della legge. Prominent inclusive positivists include Jules Coleman and H.L.A. Hart, il quale sostiene che “la norma di riconoscimento può incorporare come criterio di validità giuridica la conformità ai principi morali o ai valori sostanziali… come il sedicesimo o il diciannovesimo emendamento della Costituzione degli Stati Uniti riguardanti l’istituzione della religione o le limitazioni del diritto di voto” (Hart 1994, P. 250).
In contrasto, positivismo esclusivo (chiamato anche positivismo duro) nega che un sistema giuridico possa incorporare vincoli morali sulla validità giuridica. Exclusive positivists like Joseph Raz (1979, P. 47) subscribe to the source thesis, secondo cui l'esistenza e il contenuto del diritto possono sempre essere determinati facendo riferimento alle sue fonti senza ricorrere ad argomenti morali. Su questo punto di vista, le fonti del diritto comprendono sia le circostanze della sua promulgazione sia i relativi materiali interpretativi, come i casi giudiziari che coinvolgono la sua applicazione.
At first glance, exclusive positivism may seem difficult to reconcile with what appear to be moral criteria of legal validity in legal systems like that of the United States. Per esempio, the Fourth Amendment provides that “[t]he right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, documenti, and effects against unreasonable searches and seizures, shall not be violated.” Likewise, the First Amendment prohibits laws abridging the right of free speech. Taken at face value, these amendments seem to make moral standards part of the conditions for legal validity.
Exclusive positivists argue that such amendments can require judges to consider moral standards in certain circumstances, but cannot incorporate those standards into the law. When a judge makes reference to moral considerations in deciding a case, she necessarily creates new law on an issue-and this is so even when the law directs her to consider moral considerations, as the Bill of Rights does in certain circumstances. Su questo punto di vista, all law is settled law and questions of settled law can be resolved without recourse to moral arguments:
The law on a question is settled when legally binding sources provide its solution. In such cases judges are typically said to apply the law, and since it is source-based, its application involves technical, legal skills in reasoning from those sources and does not call for moral acumen. If a legal question is not answered by standards deriving from legal sources then it lacks a legal answer-the law on such questions is unsettled. In deciding such cases courts inevitably break new (legale) ground and their decision develops the law…. Naturally, their decisions in such cases rely at least partly on moral and other extra-legal considerations (Raz 1979, pp. 49-50).
If the judge can resolve an issue involving the First Amendment merely by applying past court decisions, then the issue is settled by the law; if not, then the issue is unsettled. Insofar as the judge looks to controversial moral standards to resolve the issue, she is going beyond the law because the mere presence of controversy about the law implies that it is indeterminate. Così, on Raz’s view, references to moral language in the law, al massimo, direct judges to consider moral requirements in resolving certain unsettled questions of law. They cannot incorporate moral requirements into the law.
3. The Discretion Thesis
Third thesis commonly associated with positivism is the discretion thesis, according to which judges decide difficult cases by making new law in the exercise of discretion. Ronald Dworkin describes this thesis as follows:
The set of these valid legal rules is exhaustive of ‘the law’, so that if someone’s case is not clearly covered by such a rule . . . then that case cannot be decided by ‘applying the law.’ It must be decided by some official, like a judge, ‘exercising his discretion,’ which means reaching beyond the law for some other sort of standard to guide him in manufacturing a fresh legal rule or supplementing an old one (Dwork nel 1977, P. 17).
Su questo punto di vista, a judge cannot decide a case that does not fall clearly under a valid rule by interpreting or applying the law; she must decide the case by creating or promulgating a law that did not exist prior to the adjudication. Così, the discretion thesis implies that judges are empowered with a quasi-legislative lawmaking authority in cases that cannot be decided merely by applying law.
Though often associated with positivism, the discretion thesis does not belong to positivism’s theoretical core. The pedigree and separability theses purport to be conceptual claims that are true of every possible legal system. These two claims jointly assert that, in every possible legal system, propositions of law are valid in virtue of having been manufactured according to some set of social conventions. Su questo punto di vista, there are no moral constraints on the content of law that hold in every possible legal system.
But many positivists regard the discretion thesis as a contingent claim that is true of some, but not all, possible legal systems. Hart, Per esempio, believes there will inevitably arise cases that do not fall clearly under a rule, but concedes a rule of recognition could deny judges discretion to make law in such cases by requiring judges “to disclaim jurisdiction or to refer the points not regulated by the existing law to the legislature to decide” (Hart 1994, P. 272). Infatti, Hart’s inclusive positivism allows him to hold that a rule of recognition could require judges to decide cases in precisely the manner that Dworkin advocates (Hart 1994, P. 263; and see Section IV-2, infra). Così, at least for inclusive positivists like Hart, the discretion thesis makes a different kind of claim than the conceptual claims that form positivism’s theoretical core (Himma 1999).
Inoltre, the discretion thesis is consistent with some forms of natural law theory. According to Blackstone’s classical naturalism, conformity with the natural law is a necessary condition for legal validity in every possible legal system. But insofar as the natural law is incomplete, there will inevitably arise issues that have multiple outcomes consistent with the natural law. Since none of the relevant outcomes in such cases offend the natural law, there is nothing in the assumption of necessary moral constraints on the content of law, in and of itself, that precludes Blackstone from endorsing the discretion thesis in such cases. Naturalmente,, if Blackstone believes the natural law contains a principle denying discretion to judges, then that commitment is inconsistent with the discretion thesis. But the assertion there are necessary constraints on the content of law, in and of itself, is consistent with the discretion thesis, even construed as a conceptual claim, as long as there are cases to which the natural law is indifferent.
In ogni caso, Dworkin distinguishes three different senses in which a judge might be said to have discretion: (1) a judge has discretion when she exercises judgment in applying a legal standard to a particular case; (2) a judge has discretion when her decision is not subject to reversal by any other authority; e (3) a judge has discretion when her decision is not bound by any legal standards.
Secondo Dworkin, positivism’s discretion thesis is committed to the third sense of discretion, which he refers to as strong discretion. Dal punto di vista di Dworkin, the thesis that judges have discretion only in the sense that they exercise judgment is trivially true, while the thesis that judges have discretion in the sense that their decisions are not subject to being reversed by a higher authority is false. Even the Supreme Court can be reversed by Congress or by constitutional amendment. Così, dal punto di vista di Dworkin, the discretion thesis implies that judges have discretion to decide hard cases by what amounts to an act of legislation because the judge is not bound by any legal standards.
Thus construed, the discretion thesis is inconsistent with ordinary legal practice. Even in the most difficult of cases where there is no clearly applicable law, lawyers do not ask that the judge decide the relevant issue by making new law. Each lawyer cites cases favorable to her client’s position and argues that the judge is bound by those cases to decide in her client’s favor. As a practical matter, lawyers rarely, se mai, concede there are no legal standards governing a case and ask the judge to legislate in the exercise of discretion.
Tuttavia, the problem with Dworkin’s analysis is that it falsely presupposes an official cannot make new law unless there are no legal standards constraining the official’s decision. Infatti, lawmaking authorities in legal systems like the U.S. never have what Dworkin describes as strong discretion. Even the legislative decisions of Congress, the highest legislative authority in the nation, are always constrained by constitutional standards. Per esempio, under the Fourteenth Amendment, Congress cannot enact a law that sets one speed limit for male drivers on interstate highways and another for female drivers.
Da parte sua, Hart concedes that judicial lawmaking authority is limited in two respects: “not only are the judge’s powers subject to many constraints narrowing his choice from which a legislature may be quite free, but since the judge’s powers are exercised only to dispose of particular instant cases he cannot use these to introduce large-scale reforms or new codes” (Hart 1994, P. 273). What explains the judge’s discretion to make new law in a given case, dal punto di vista di Hart, is not the absence of legal standards constraining her decision; rather it is the absence of legal standards that dictate a uniquely correct answer to the case. The judge cannot decide such a case merely by applying existing law because there is more than one available outcome that coheres with existing law. In such instances, it is impossible to render a substantive decision (as opposed to simply referring the matter back to the legislature) without creating new law.
The discretion thesis is vulnerable to one powerful objection. Insofar as a judge decides a difficult case by making new law in the exercise of discretion, the case is being decided on the basis of a law that did not exist at the time the dispute arose. Se, Per esempio, a judge awards damages to a plaintiff by making new law in the exercise of discretion, it follows that she has held the defendant liable under a law that did not exist at the time the dispute arose. E, as Dworkin points out, it seems patently unfair to deprive a defendant of property for behavior that did not give rise to liability at the time the behavior occurred.
Tuttavia, Dworkin’s view fares no better on this count. While Dworkin acknowledges the existence of difficult cases that do not fall clearly under a rule, he believes they are not resolved by an exercise of judicial discretion. Dal punto di vista di Dworkin, there is always a right answer to such cases implicit in the pre-existing law. Naturalmente,, it sometimes takes a judge of Herculean intellectual ability to discern what the right answer is, but it is always there to be found in pre-existing law. Since the right answer to even hard legal disputes is always part of pre-existing law, Dworkin believes that a judge can take property from a defendant in a hard case without unfairness (Dwork nel 1977, pp. 87-130).
But if fairness precludes taking property from a defendant under a law that did not exist at the time of the relevant behavior, it also precludes taking property from a defendant under a law that did not give reasonable notice that the relevant behavior gives rise to liability. Due process and fundamental fairness require reasonable notice of which behaviors give rise to liability. As long as Dworkin acknowledges the existence of cases so difficult that only the best of judges can solve them, his theory is vulnerable to the same charge of unfairness that he levels at the discretion thesis.
4. Classic Criticisms of Positivism
UN. Fuller’s Internal Morality of Law
In The Morality of Law, Su l. Fuller argues that law is subject to an internal morality consisting of eight principles: (P1) le regole devono essere espresse in termini generali; (P2) le regole devono essere promulgate pubblicamente; (P3) the rules must be (per la maggior parte) prospective in effect; (P4) le regole devono essere espresse in termini comprensibili; (P5) le regole devono essere coerenti tra loro; (P6) le norme non devono imporre comportamenti che esulano dai poteri delle parti interessate; (P7) le regole non devono essere cambiate così frequentemente che il soggetto non possa fare affidamento su di esse; e (P8) le norme devono essere amministrate in modo coerente con la loro formulazione (Fuller 1964, P. 39).
Dal punto di vista di Fuller, nessun sistema di regole che non riesca a soddisfare minimamente questi principi di legalità può raggiungere lo scopo essenziale del diritto di realizzare l’ordine sociale attraverso l’uso di regole che guidano il comportamento. Un sistema di regole che non riesce a soddisfare (P2) o (P4), Per esempio, non possono guidare il comportamento perché le persone non saranno in grado di determinare cosa richiedono le regole. Di conseguenza, Fuller conclude che i suoi otto principi sono “interni” al diritto, nel senso che sono integrati nelle condizioni di esistenza del diritto.: “Un fallimento totale in una qualsiasi di queste otto direzioni non si traduce semplicemente in un cattivo sistema giuridico; il risultato è qualcosa che non è propriamente chiamato sistema legale” (Fuller 1964, P. 39).
These internal principles constitute a morality, according to Fuller, because law necessarily has positive moral value in two respects: (1) law conduces to a state of social order and (2) does so by respecting human autonomy because rules guide behavior. Since no system of rules can achieve these morally valuable objectives without minimally complying with the principles of legality, segue, on Fuller’s view, that they constitute a morality. Since these moral principles are built into the existence conditions for law, they are internal and hence represent a conceptual connection between law and morality that is inconsistent with the separability thesis.
Hart responds by denying Fuller’s claim that the principles of legality constitute an internal morality; dal punto di vista di Hart, Fuller confuses the notions of morality and efficacy:
[T]he author’s insistence on classifying these principles of legality as a “morality” is a source of confusion both for him and his readers…. [T]he crucial objection to the designation of these principles of good legal craftsmanship as morality, in spite of the qualification “inner,” is that it perpetrates a confusion between two notions that it is vital to hold apart: the notions of purposive activity and morality. Poisoning is no doubt a purposive activity, and reflections on its purpose may show that it has its internal principles. (“Avoid poisons however lethal if they cause the victim to vomit”….) But to call these principles of the poisoner’s art “the morality of poisoning” would simply blur the distinction between the notion of efficiency for a purpose and those final judgments about activities and purposes with which morality in its various forms is concerned (Hart 1965, pp. 1285-86).
Dal punto di vista di Hart, all actions, including virtuous acts like lawmaking and impermissible acts like poisoning, have their own internal standards of efficacy. But insofar as such standards of efficacy conflict with morality, as they do in the case of poisoning, it follows that they are distinct from moral standards. Così, while Hart concedes that something like Fuller’s eight principles are built into the existence conditions for law, he concludes that they do not constitute a conceptual connection between law and morality.
Purtroppo, Hart’s response overlooks the fact that most of Fuller’s eight principles double as moral ideals of fairness. Per esempio, public promulgation in understandable terms may be a necessary condition for efficacy, but it is also a moral ideal; it is morally objectionable for a state to enforce rules that have not been publicly promulgated in terms reasonably calculated to give notice of what is required. Allo stesso modo, we take it for granted that it is wrong for a state to enact retroactive rules, inconsistent rules, and rules that require what is impossible. Poisoning may have its internal standards of efficacy, but such standards are distinguishable from the principles of legality in that they conflict with moral ideals.
Tuttavia, Fuller’s principles operate internally, not as moral ideals, but merely as principles of efficacy. As Fuller would likely acknowledge, the existence of a legal system is consistent with considerable divergence from the principles of legality. Legal standards, Per esempio, are necessarily promulgated in general terms that inevitably give rise to problems of vagueness. And officials all too often fail to administer the laws in a fair and even-handed manner-even in the best of legal systems. These divergences may always be prima facie objectionable, but they are inconsistent with a legal system only when they render a legal system incapable of performing its essential function of guiding behavior. Insofar as these principles are built into the existence conditions for law, it is because they operate as efficacy conditions-and not because they function as moral ideals.
Fuller’s jurisprudential legacy, Tuttavia, should not be underestimated. While positivists have long acknowledged that law’s essential purpose is to guide behavior through rules (per esempio., John Austin writes that “[UN] law .. may be defined as a rule laid down for the guidance of an intelligent being by an intelligent being having power over him” Austin 1977, P. 5), they have not always appreciated the implications of this purpose. Fuller’s lasting contribution to the theory of law was to flesh out these implications in the form of his principles of legality.
b. Positivism and Legal Principles
Dworkin argues that, in deciding hard cases, judges often invoke legal principles that do not derive their authority from an official act of promulgation (Dwork nel 1977, P. 40). These principles, Dworkin believes, must be characterized as law because judges are bound to consider them when relevant. But if unpromulgated legal principles constitute law, then it is false, contra the pedigree thesis, that a proposition of law is valid only in virtue of having been formally promulgated.
Secondo Dworkin, principles and rules differ in the kind of guidance they provide to judges:
Rules are applicable in an all-or-nothing fashion. If the facts a rule stipulates are given, then either the rule is valid, in which case the answer it supplies must be accepted, or it is not, in which case it contributes nothing to the decision…. But this is not the way principles operate…. [A principle] states a reason that argues in one direction, but does not necessitate a particular decision (Dwork nel 1977, pp. 24-25).
Dal punto di vista di Dworkin, conflicting principles provide competing reasons that must be weighed according to the importance of the respective values they express. Così, rules are distinguishable from principles in two related respects: (1) rules necessitate, where principles only suggest, a particular outcome; e (2) principles have, where rules lack, the dimension of weight.
Dworkin cites the case of Riggs v. Palmer as representative of how judges use principles to decide hard cases. In Riggs, the court considered the question of whether a murderer could take under the will of his victim. At the time the case was decided, neither the statutes nor the case law governing wills expressly prohibited a murderer from taking under his victim’s will. Nonostante questo, the court declined to award the defendant his gift under the will on the ground that it would be wrong to allow him to profit from such a grievous wrong. Dal punto di vista di Dworkin, the court decided the case by citing “the principle that no man may profit from his own wrong as a background standard against which to read the statute of wills and in this way justified a new interpretation of that statute” (Dwork nel 1977, P. 29).
The positivist might respond that when the Riggs court considered this principle, it was reaching beyond the law to extralegal standards in the exercise of judicial discretion. But Dworkin points out that the Riggs judges would “rightfully” have been criticized had they failed to consider this principle; if it were merely an extralegal standard, there would be no rightful grounds to criticize a failure to consider it (Dwork nel 1977, P. 35). Di conseguenza, Dworkin concludes that the best explanation for the propriety of such criticism is that principles are part of the law.
Ulteriore, Dworkin maintains that the legal authority of standards like the Riggs principle cannot derive from promulgation in accordance with purely formal requirements: “[e]ven though principles draw support from the official acts of legal institutions, they do not have a simple or direct enough connection with these acts to frame that connection in terms of criteria specified by some ultimate master rule of recognition” (Dwork nel 1977, P. 41). Unlike legal rules, legal principles lack a canonical form and hence cannot be explained by formal promulgation.
Dal punto di vista di Dworkin, l’autorità giuridica di un principio vincolante deriva dal contributo che esso fornisce alla migliore giustificazione morale delle pratiche giuridiche di una società considerata nel suo insieme. Secondo Dworkin, un principio giuridico contribuisce al massimo a tale giustificazione se e solo se soddisfa due condizioni: (1) il principio è coerente con il materiale giuridico esistente; e (2) il principio è lo standard moralmente più attraente che soddisfa (1). Il principio giuridico corretto è quello che rende la legge la migliore morale possibile. Così, conclude Dworkin, “Se trattiamo i principi come legge dobbiamo respingere il primo principio dei positivisti, che il diritto di una comunità si distingue dalle altre norme sociali mediante qualche criterio sotto forma di regola generale” (Dwork nel 1977, P. 44).
In risposta, positivists concede that there are legal principles, but argue that their authority as law can be explained in terms of the conventions contained in the rule of recognition:
Legal principles, like other laws, can be enacted or repealed by legislatures and administrative authorities. They can also become legally binding through establishment by the courts. Many legal systems recognize that both rules and principles can be made into law or lose their status as law through precedent (Raz 1972, P. 848).
Secondo questo punto di vista, legal principles are like legal rules in that both derive their authority under the rule of recognition from the official acts of courts and legislatures. If the Riggs principle that no person shall profit from her own wrong has legal authority, it is because that principle was either declared by a court in the course of adjudicating a dispute or formally promulgated by the appropriate legislative body.
Ulteriore, inclusive positivists argue that Dworkin’s account of principles is itself consistent with the pedigree thesis. As Hart puts it, “this interpretative test seems not to be an alternative to a criterion provided by a rule of recognition, but … only a complex ‘soft-positivist’ form of such a criterion identifying principles by their content not by their pedigree” (Hart 1994, P. 263). The idea, familiar from Section II, is that a rule of recognition can incorporate content-based constraints on legal validity, even those rooted ultimately in morality.
c. The Semantic Sting
In Law’s Empire, Dworkin distinguishes two kinds of disagreement legal practitioners can have about the law. Lawyers can agree on the criteria a rule must satisfy to be legally valid, but disagree on whether those criteria are satisfied by a particular rule. Per esempio, two lawyers might agree that a rule is valid if enacted by the state legislature, but disagree on whether the rule at issue was actually enacted by the state legislature. Such disagreements are empirical in nature and hence pose no theoretical difficulties for positivism.
C'è, Tuttavia, a second kind of disagreement that Dworkin believes is inconsistent with positivism. Lawyers often agree on the facts about a rule’s creation, but disagree on whether those facts are sufficient to endow the rule with legal authority. Such disagreement is considerably deeper than empirical disagreement as it concerns the criteria for legal validity-which, according to positivism, are exhausted by the rule of recognition. Dworkin calls this second kind of disagreement theoretical disagreement about the law.
Theoretical disagreement, dal punto di vista di Dworkin, is inconsistent with the pedigree thesis because the pedigree thesis explains the concept of law in terms of shared criteria for creating, modificare e giudicare la legge:
If legal argument is mainly or even partly about [the properties that make a proposition legally valid], then lawyers cannot all be using the same factual criteria for deciding when propositions of law are true and false. Their arguments would be mainly or partly about which criteria they should use. So the project of the semantic theories, the project of digging out shared rules from a careful study of what lawyers say and do, would be doomed to fail (Dwork nel 1986, P. 43).
If lawyers disagree about the criteria of legal validity, then the grounds of legal validity cannot be exhausted by the shared criteria contained in a rule of recognition. The semantic sting, Poi, implies that there must be more to the concept of legal validity than can be explained by promulgation in accordance with shared criteria embodied in a rule of recognition.
The semantic sting resembles one of Dworkin’s earlier criticisms of Hart’s pedigree thesis. Hart believes that the rule of recognition is a social rule and is hence constituted by the conforming behavior of people who also accept the rule as a ground for criticizing deviations. Like all social rules, Poi, the rule of recognition has an external and internal aspect. The external aspect of the rule of recognition consists in general obedience to those rules satisfying its criteria of validity; the internal aspect is constituted by its acceptance as a public standard of official behavior. Hart believes it is this double aspect of the rule of recognition that accounts for its normativity and enables him to distinguish his theory from Austin’s view of law as a system of coercive commands. Per, as Hart points out, a purely coercive command can oblige, but never obligate, a person to comply (see Section I, supra).
Dworkin argues that this feature of Hart’s theory commits him to the claim that there cannot be any disagreement about the content of rule of recognition:
Hart’s qualification … that the rule of recognition may be uncertain at particular points … undermines [his theory]…. If judges are in fact divided about what they must do if a subsequent Parliament tries to repeal an entrenched rule, then it is not uncertain whether any social rule [of recognition] governs that decision; on the contrary, it is certain that none does (Dwork nel 1977, pp. 61-62).
Dal punto di vista di Dworkin, the requirements of a social rule cannot be uncertain since a social rule is constituted by acceptance and conforming behavior by most people in the relevant group: “two people whose rules differ … cannot be appealing to the same social rule, and at least one of them cannot be appealing to any social rule at all” (Dwork nel 1977, P. 55).
Jules Coleman responds that if the rule of recognition is a social rule, then Hart’s view implies there must be general agreement among the officials of a legal system about what standards constitute the rule of recognition, but it does not imply there cannot be disagreement as to what those standards require in any given instance:
The controversy among judges does not arise over the content of the rule of recognition itself. It arises over which norms satisfy the standards set forth in it. The divergence in behavior among officials as exemplified in their identifying different standards as legal ones does not establish their failure to accept the same rule of recognition. Anzi, judges accept the same truth conditions for propositions of law…. They disagree about which propositions satisfy those conditions (Coleman 1982, P. 156).
Coleman, Poi, distinguishes two kinds of disagreement practitioners can have about the rule of recognition: (1) disagreement about what standards constitute the rule of recognition; e (2) disagreement about what propositions satisfy those standards. On Coleman’s view, Hart’s analysis of social rules implies only that (1) is impossible.
Under the U.S. rule of recognition, Per esempio, a federal statute is legally valid if and only if it has been enacted in accordance with the procedural requirements described in the body of the Constitution and is consistent with the first fourteen amendments. Da, dal punto di vista di Hart, gli Stati Uniti. rule of recognition is a social rule, U.S. officials must agree on the procedures the federal government must follow in enacting law, the set of sentences constituting the first fourteen amendments, and the requirement that federal enactments be consistent with those amendments.
But Hart’s view of social rules does not imply there cannot be any disagreement about whether a given enactment is consistent with the first fourteen amendments. Legal practitioners can and do disagree on what Hart calls penumbral (or borderline) issues regarding the various amendments. While every competent practitioner in the U.S. would agree, Per esempio, that torturing a person to induce a confession violates the fifth amendment right against self-incrimination, there is considerable disagreement about whether compelling a defendant to undergo a psychiatric examination for the purpose of increasing her sentence also violates that right. On Coleman’s view, there is nothing in Hart’s analysis of social rules that precludes such borderline disagreements about whether a practice is consistent with the Fifth Amendment.
Despite its resemblance to this earlier criticism, Dworkin’s semantic sting argument takes aim at a deeper target. The semantic sting targets all so-called semantic theories of law that articulate the concept of law in terms of “shared rules … that set out criteria that supply the word’s meaning” (Dwork nel 1986, P. 31). Così, while the earlier criticism is directed at Hart’s extraneous account of social rules, the semantic sting is directed at what Dworkin takes to be the very heart of positivism’s theoretical core, vale a dire, the claim that there are shared criteria that exhaust the conditions for the correct application of the concept of law.
At the root of the problem with semantic theories, dal punto di vista di Dworkin, is a flawed theory of what makes disagreement possible. Secondo Dworkin, semantic theories mistakenly assume that meaningful disagreement is impossible unless “we all accept and follow the same criteria for deciding when our claims are sound, even if we cannot state exactly, as a philosopher might hope to do, what these criteria are” (Dwork nel 1986, P. 45). On this flawed assumption, two people whose concepts of law differ cannot be disagreeing about the same thing.
Perhaps with Coleman’s response to his earlier criticism in mind, Dworkin concedes that semantic theories are consistent with theoretical disagreements about borderline or penumbral cases: “people do sometimes speak at cross-purposes in the way the borderline defense describes” (Dwork nel 1986, P. 41). But Dworkin denies semantic theories are consistent with theoretical disagreement about pivotal (or core) cases. According to semantic theories, lui dice,
[E]ou and I can sensibly discuss how many books I have on my shelf, Per esempio, only if we both agree, at least roughly, about what a book is. We can disagree over borderline cases: I may call something a slim book that you would call a pamphlet. But we cannot disagree over what I called pivotal cases. If you do not count my copy of Moby-Dick as a book because in your view novels are not books, any disagreement is bound to be senseless (Dwork nel 1986, P. 45).
Il problema, dal punto di vista di Dworkin, is that many difficult appellate cases like Riggs involve theoretical disagreement about pivotal cases:
The various judges who argued about our sample cases did not think they were defending marginal or borderline claims. Their disagreements about legislation and precedent were fundamental; their arguments showed that they disagreed not only about whether Elmer should have his inheritance, but about why any legislative act, even traffic codes and rates of taxation, impose the rights and obligations everyone agrees they do…. They disagreed about what makes a proposition of law true not just at the margin but in the core as well (Dwork nel 1986, pp. 42-43).
Dal punto di vista di Dworkin, the judges in Riggs were not having a borderline dispute about some accepted criterion for the application of the concept of law. Piuttosto, they were having a disagreement about the status of some putatively fundamental criterion itself: the majority believed, while the dissent denied, that courts have power to modify unambiguous legislative enactments.
Di conseguenza, theoretical disagreement about pivotal cases like Riggs is inconsistent with semantic theories of law, dal punto di vista di Dworkin, because it shows that shared criteria do not exhaust the proper conditions for the application of the concept of law. For the majority and dissenting judges in Riggs were having a sensible disagreement about law even though it centered on a pivotal case involving the criteria of legal validity. Così, conclude Dworkin, the concept of law cannot be explained by so-called criterial semantics.
In risposta, Hart denies both that his theory is a semantic theory and that it assumes such an account of what makes disagreement possible:
[N]othing in my book or in anything else I have written supports [a semantic account] of my theory. Così, my doctrine that developed municipal legal systems contain a rule of recognition specifying the criteria for the identification of the laws which courts have to apply may be mistaken, but I nowhere base this doctrine on the mistaken idea that it is part of the meaning of the word ‘law’ that there should be such a rule of recognition in all legal systems, or on the even more mistaken idea that if the criteria for the identification of the grounds of law were not uncontroversially fixed, ‘law’ would mean different things to different people (Hart 1994, P. 246).
Invece, Hart argues that his theory of law is “a descriptive account of the distinctive features of law in general as a complex social phenomenon” (Hart 1994, P. 246). Hart presents his theory, not as an account of how people apply the concept of law, but rather as an account of what distinguishes systems of law from other systems of social rules. Dal punto di vista di Hart, it is the presence of a rule of recognition establishing criteria of validity that distinguishes law from other systems of social rules. Così, according to Hart, Dworkin’s criticism fails because it mischaracterizes positivism as providing a criterial explanation of the concept of law.
5. Riferimenti e approfondimenti
Austin, John, Lezioni di giurisprudenza e di filosofia del diritto positivo (S. Clair Shores, MI: Stampa accademica, 1977)
Austin, John, La provincia della giurisprudenza determinata (Cambridge: Pressa dell'Università di Cambridge, 1995)
Bentham, Jeremy, Delle leggi in generale (Londra: Athlone Press, 1970)
Blackstone, Guglielmo, Commentari sulla legge d'Inghilterra (Chicago: La stampa dell'Università di Chicago, 1979)
Coleman, Jules, “Positivismo negativo e positivo,” 11 Journal of Legal Studies 139 (1982)
Dworkin, Ronald M., L’impero della legge (Cambridge: Stampa dell'Università di Harvard, 1986)
Dworkin, Ronald M., Prendere sul serio i diritti (Cambridge: Stampa dell'Università di Harvard, 1977)
Finnis, John, Diritto naturale e diritti naturali (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)
Più pieno, Lon L., La moralità del diritto, Revised Edition (Nuovo paradiso: Stampa dell'Università di Yale, 1969)
Più pieno, Lon L., “Positivism and Fidelity to Law–A Reply to Professor Hart,” 71 Harvard Law Review 630 (1958)
Faber, Klaus, “Addio al “positivismo giuridico”: The Separation Thesis Unraveling,” in George, Robert P., L'autonomia del diritto: Saggi sul positivismo giuridico (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 119-162
Giorgio, Robert P., “Natural Law and Positive Law,” in George, Robert P., L'autonomia del diritto: Saggi sul positivismo giuridico (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 321-334
Hart, H.L.A., Il concetto di diritto, Seconda edizione (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994)
Hart, H.L.A., “American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream,” reprinted in Hart, H.L.A., Saggi di giurisprudenza e filosofia (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 123-144.
Hart, H.L.A., “Book Review of The Morality of Law” 78 Harvard Law Review 1281 (1965)
Hart, H.L.A., Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982)
Hart, H.L.A., “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” 71 Harvard Law Review 593 (1958)
Iniziativa, Kenneth E., “Judicial Discretion and the Concept of Law,” forthcoming in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies vol. 18, NO. 1 (1999)
Mackie, J.L., “The Third Theory of Law,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, vol. 7, NO. 1 (Fall 1977)
Moore, Michael, “Il diritto come forma funzionale,” in George, Robert P. (ed.), Teoria del diritto naturale: Saggi contemporanei (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 188-242
Raz, Joseph, L'autorità della legge: Saggi su diritto e moralità (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979)
Raz, Joseph, “Authority, Law and Morality,"Il monista, vol. 68, 295-324
Raz, Joseph, “Legal Principles and the Limits of Law,” 81 Yale Law Review 823 (1972)
Raz, Joseph, “Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison,"Teoria giuridica, vol. 4, NO. 3 (September 1998), 249-282
Waluchow, W.J., Positivismo giuridico inclusivo (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994)
Informazioni sull'autore
Kenneth Einar Himma
E-mail: [email protected]
Università del Pacifico di Seattle
U. S. UN.